Part 1: "Underground"
Part 1, Chapter 1
The first thing we find out about the narrator is that he is spiteful and physically ill. Moreover, he is very self-conscious, very aware of this spitefulness that belongs to him. He explains that he was a rather badly behaved civil servant who took pleasure in causing distress to others who needed his help. But he can't even really enter into his own spitefulness since as he tells us, it was all sort of an act: "not only was I not a spiteful man, I was not even an embittered one… (1307). This narrator, it quickly becomes apparent, likes to make bold assertions and then take them back or at least modify them – he is obviously unreliable. He speaks of "contradictory elements" (1308) in his nature, and these elements torment him.
The inability to act is the next thing the narrator
explains following upon his stated realization that he can't either embrace
spitefulness or become good – he is always uncomfortably somewhere in between
the hero and the rascal. And here we are
introduced to the notion that intelligence is more a curse than a blessing – a
smart man can't do anything or become anything, while fools skate through life
always certain of themselves. To be
intelligent is to have no character and therefore strangely unlimited and
undelimited, while the man of action is limited. He used to be a collegiate assessor, but a
relative left him 6000 rubles, so he retired last year, and now lives in expensive
St. Petersburg. The first chapter ends
with a tricky rejection of the discourse of "a decent man" – the
decent man takes pleasure in talking about himself, and our narrator says,
"I too will talk about myself" (1308).
Part 1, Chapter 2
To be overly conscious is a disease (1309 top). The more conscious the narrator became about
the beautiful and the sublime, about the good, the less able he was to act, and
thus he became bitter. But finally,
after much struggle, this bitterness becomes sweetness and finally pleasure
(1310 top). Is it the same for
others? He wants to know. As for the pleasure he is talking about, we
are told that it came from "the overly acute consciousness of one's own
humiliation…" (1310). You can't
change, and you can't do anything, so why not be a scoundrel? He declares his aim to be explaining the kind
of pleasure he is talking about, the perverse pleasure in one's own humiliation
and incapacity to do anything about it.
Part 1, Chapter 3
What do normal people do when they run into natural
limits, into a brick wall imposed upon them by nature itself? Well, normal, probably stupid people,
according to our narrator, simply give up.
He calls these people "spontaneous" (1311), and says that the
wall, for them, is definitive and meaningful, even "mystical" (1311). It is not so for a mouse like our narrator –
for that is what he calls himself. This
mouse has what the narrator calls "overly acute consciousness"
(1311), meaning that he is highly self-conscious, self-aware. This mouse cannot even work up and execute a
plan for revenge the way the so-called "man of nature and truth" can;
that is because the mouse knows that revenge is wrong, or at least that it
makes no sense to call it justice. So he
cannot act, and seethes with resentment (1311).
This is the origin of spitefulness and resentment, an important quality
to our narrator, even though as his reasoning progresses, he demonstrates a
conviction that spitefulness, like other supposed reasons, is ultimately hollow
because it requires an agent that the spiteful but intelligent man simply does
not believe in.
But here things become even more complicated because
our mouse starts to take a certain pleasure in his own predicament, his own
feeling of being done an injustice and yet not having the ability to do
anything about it. See page 1312 on
this, and 1313 for the narrator's explanation: he doesn't care about the laws
of nature or that 2+2 make 4; the thing is, he dislikes such laws and that is
what matters most. It is better, he
thinks, to refuse reconciliation with the laws of nature, mathematics, natural
science, and so forth, better to oppose them all so long as you can maintain a
certain independence of thought and will.
Simply not to be an absolute dupe seems to be his goal, and to achieve
it he sets himself against the cosmos and other men. There is bitter pleasure in this. The narrator is not asserting that he is in
possession of any grand systematic truth.
Far from it.
Part 1, Chapter 4
The narrator insists further that even consciousness of pain can lead to a kind of voluptuous pleasure – it is precisely the fact that you know there's no one to blame for your toothache that you betray by moaning about it. Nature can inflict all sorts of injuries and humiliations upon you and your body, even if you despise nature. There's nothing you can do about it, and perhaps that is what eventually leads to this strange pleasurable sensation or enjoyment. See page 1314 in particular: the enjoyment becomes downright voluptuous, says the narrator, when, say, the 19th-century man moaning about his toothache becomes fully aware that the moaning accomplishes nothing but to annoy everyone around him. He knows he's just acting spitefully and maliciously, and that is what he takes such great pleasure in: it is a kind of knowledge, admirable or otherwise. The narrator really drills home the point when he asks at the very end of the fourth chapter, "Can a man possessing consciousness ever really respect himself?" To be self-conscious makes it impossible to have self-respect. Apparently, only healthy, normal idiots respect themselves. So why be normal? To be normal is to live comfortably within one's petty performances, one's illusions, always to be surrounded by the paper bag of unalterable reality.
Part 1, Chapter 5
The narrator describes boredom as central to his consciousness – he has always found himself stirring up trouble, getting emotionally involved in things he doesn't really care about, and so forth, simply to escape this boredom for a moment. The excess of consciousness that structures his being leads, as he says, to "inertia" (1315). The normal, stupid person has little trouble finding a foundation or a secure basis for action in the world, but clever individuals understand that there is probably no such foundation, that there are most likely only "immediate and secondary causes" (1315), at least as far as we can know. Justice would be a primary cause, but that is exactly the sort of thing our mouse can never find fully justified, cannot discover – there is only an infinite succession backwards of secondary causes. You might think spite could stand in for a primary cause, but the problem is that it disintegrates pretty quickly, and you are left with nothing but contempt for yourself for having believed it could serve as a foundation for action. Strong negative emotions, in other words, soon burn themselves out, and you can't really maintain them as the basis for sustained action. So we are back to inertia again. That is hardly surprising: the narrator can't set forth any of his claims in terms of the primary causality that makes it possible for "normal people" to act. The underground man can never act, speak or write in perfect faith in the justice of his beliefs or words.
Part 1, Chapter 6
If only, says the narrator, he could pinpoint the reason for his inactivity as laziness. But he cannot even do that. A person can make a fine career out of laziness, and be well respected for it. You could for example be a connoisseur or art critic who simply affirms what everybody else thinks constitutes "the beautiful and sublime" (1316). That way, you become part of a social system revolving around groupthink, aesthetical or otherwise. If you don't mind going along, it's very easy to get along and prosper.
Part 1, Chapter 7
Plato's notion that enlightenment is the key to the
good society because people always act in their own self-interest seems
ridiculous to our narrator, who insists that history proves quite
otherwise. What's the value in
constructing utopias, in that case? No
value. The greatest advantage of all,
the one beyond any "rational, advantageous desire," is "independent desire" (1320). To follow your own will, even if it takes you
off the edge of a cliff – that, I think our narrator is saying, is the key to
human existence and it annihilates all utopias from the time of Plato onwards.
Part 1, Chapter 8
But what if even free will, which are narrator has
been so energetically promoting, turns out to be an illusion? What if science destroys any possible belief
in it? What if desire itself is nothing
but the slave of necessity? Desire is
irrational, and that is its chief virtue – the narrator says that reason is
only one dimension of life and that desire is much more pervasive; it is
"a manifestation of all life" (1321).
Another key statement: humanity is defined as "a creature that walks
on two legs and is ungrateful" – but more particularly, perpetually badly
behaved (1322). We really do not act in
our own best interests, either collectively or as individuals. The key to this chapter appears towards its
conclusion: even if we could predict and tabulate all the motions of human
desire, even if we turned out to be piano keys played upon by the alleged laws
of nature, we would go so far as to abandon sanity itself to escape
determination and predictability. Threatened
with being the slave of necessity, or 2+2, so to speak, man will curse, cause
disturbances, stir up trouble, defy and make those things the meaning of his
existence. What would be the point of
desire if it were not unpredictable, if it were reducible to an algorithm of
the laws of nature? 2+2 always make 4,
even if your will has nothing to do with it, so why align yourself with the
laws of mathematics and nature?
Part 1, Chapter 9
The narrator contrasts us with ants making their
anthills. The difference is that they
keep doing the same thing and their purpose is completely utilitarian. They're going to make good use of the
anthills that they build and will keep doing so until there are no more
ants. But for us, achieving the goal of
our constructions is the beginning of death, just as 2+2 make 4 is "the
beginning of death" (1324).
Consciousness is a curse, but at the same time, we would not give it up,
and it is "higher than two times two" (1325).
Part 1, Chapter 10
The Crystal Palace is really not as useful as a
chicken coop, says the narrator, and at least the chicken coop isn't terrifying
in its implications for free will and desire.
It is impossible to stick out one's tongue at such a palace (1325). And in the end, this palace really is a
chicken coop because it shelters us from the truth that we are nothing more
than dupes, is just an illusion that we cherish, an illusion of purpose and
perpetual progress. The narrator
concludes this chapter by recognizing just how dangerous his own brand of thinking
is to everyone who is not like him (1326).
Part 1, Chapter 11
In this final chapter of the first part, the
narrator explains what to some degree he has meant all along by "the
underground": he apparently means by this phrase in part thinking itself,
but we should add that this thinking is dialogical, meaning that he imagines an
audience in response to it. To this
audience he declares that "it's better to do nothing! Conscious inertia is better!" (1326) There is something of the back and
forth of conversation going on in this so-called underground. The underground is everything that healthy,
normal people repress as they go about their waking lives and business – they
have no need of such philosophizing and agonizing over things like purpose and
free will. It's what mustn't be uttered,
perhaps even what shouldn't be thought, lest one suffer the psychological
consequences. The narrator insists that
he will never print his words and share them with the public, which privacy-device
creates a sense of intimacy as we read – it is as if we are not the reading
public but rather individuals who have somehow come by this unpublished
manuscript, which itself seems to be the effusion of a man who has been
underground for his entire life.
Why not just recall it in his head, if he doesn't
mean to publish? The narrator doesn't give
a solid answer to this question, but tells us that perhaps recalling old
memories will provide some relief and allow him to get rid of those memories
once and for all. This is an ancient
concept of writing, in which the act of writing cuts off a stream of thought
from consciousness, alienating it forever from its producer. That is more or less what Plato makes
Socrates say in Phaedrus about the
invention and act of writing. And of
course the narrator is simply bored, so setting down his tale will give him
something to do: maybe in that sense it is an act of mischief, just as he said
earlier about how we deal with boredom.
Does the tale that follows reinforce the philosophy that he has set down
with such deliberate lack of systematic rigor?
That remains to be seen, but in general, it seems to back up the first
part of the text.
Part 2: "Apropos of the Wet Snow"
Part 2, Chapter 1
At the age of 24, the narrator was outwardly
conventional; the unsettling thing that comes out here is how much of the
"underground" was already within him, though it may have structured
his life at that point more or less in the form of social awkwardness, the
inability to meet the gaze of other people, etc. Even the normal activities in which the young
narrator engaged were already manifestations of his resentment and defiance of
all things conventional.
The section in which the
officer picks him up like a puffball and moves him aside is hilarious. The big fellow is like a force of nature: there's
no point in resisting him because he's a healthy, normal blockhead who probably
wouldn't accepting a challenge from a resentful man-mouse like our narrator. He didn't even seem to notice the actual bump
that the narrator finally manages to give him after two years or so, in an
attempt to turn the affair into something suitably romantic, suitably honorable
and literary. In other words, he's
trying to transform his sordid, petty reality into something heroic, to creat a
situation in which he would be the equal of the blockhead officer. Along the way, there's the delicious, bitter
pleasure of his own self-conscious state of humiliation: all those abortive
attempts before the final impetuous one (1336).
If we can say there's a pattern of behavior in this second part, it's
something like the following: self-reflection, resentment, boredom with it all,
an attempt to get outside one's head, an action at last taken, followed by consequent
withdrawal and return to inertia or some other escapist state of mind.
Part 2, Chapter 2
The narrator withdraws into a fantasy world of
romantic reveries about heroism. He goes
to see Setochkin and, more importantly for the rest of the narrative, visits Simonov,
his old friend from school days.
Part 2, Chapter 3
We learn quite a bit about the narrator's early
years: he was sent to school by distant relatives, and felt abandoned. Much of his present character stems from
those school years – his contempt for his fellow students and yet his desire to
be recognized by them, even to conquer them after a fashion. He becomes studious because they aren't. Even as he plans to attend the dinner for the
shallow, handsome officer Zverkov, he senses the hollowness of the whole
enterprise; that is, putting one over on his old "frenemies" by
insisting on attending a dinner to which he hasn't been invited. I love the fact that the friends already at
Simonov's for the initial meeting, Ferfichkin and Trudolyubov, scarcely
acknowledge his presence even though he hasn't seen them for years (). All of these so-called friends, of course,
and especially the as-yet absent Zverkov, represent stupid acceptance of
reality and the limitedness of all that is healthy and normal.
Part 2, Chapter 4
The narrator shows up early to dinner since he has
not been told about the one-hour time change (1345). The better part of the chapter centers on the
humiliation of this and indeed of the whole evening. Zverkov's infinitely stupid condescension
figures heavily (1346), and so does the bickering of his other friends along
with his own attempt to insult Zverkov, which is initially (1349) and then
subsequently rebuffed (1351). In the
end, the narrator is ignored. Although
he wrangles six rubles to follow his frenemies to the brothel they have gone to,
his request for reconciliation is refused by Zverkov (1351 top).
Part 2, Chapter 5
The narrator keeps patterning his plans after great
Russian literary works such as Masquerade
by Lermontov (1353). Life imitates art,
or at least it would if the narrator had any courage. His confrontation with so-called reality
(1351) nets him not the opportunity to slap Zverkov but rather a chance meeting
with Liza, a humble prostitute. He will
take out his anger and resentment on her since Zverkov is unavailable.
Part 2, Chapter 6
The narrator's conversation with Liza begins here,
with an inward realization of just how stupid his own debauchery is (1355
middle). The conversation continues and
the narrator's goal is to save Liza after the manner of a Russian hero (1357). It seems that he has sexual relations with
her in the course of this meeting (1358).
He sets before her the image of a happy family life, and paints for her
the horrid prospect of continuing on in this lifestyle (1360-61). At first he fails to understand that Liza's
sarcasm is only a cover for genuine feeling.
He knows that his own rhetoric is what she says: something straight out
of a book. It's cheap talk, and hardly
sincere.
Part 2, Chapter 7
Liza continues to be subjected to the narrator's
harangue, and the pitch reaches its sentimental crescendo (1364 top). The narrator even finds that he responds to
his own emotional words. This rhetoric
is effective with Liza since it seems to be what she needed to hear in her
real-life context. There is irony in the
sense the narrator has so often tried to pattern his life, unsuccessfully
enough, after literary texts. Liza
touchingly shows the narrator the letter she received from a gentleman caller
who knows nothing of her sordid present (1365).
While leaving, the narrator realizes "the truth" about this
whole encounter – as he will say in the next chapter, it has all been nothing
but sentimentality, fundamentally insincere.
Part 2, Chapter 8
The narrator writes to S and pays his debt with borrowed money. But he is still tormented by thoughts about
Liza, about her pathetic match-light smile, and obsesses over being found out
in his cheap apartment. He continues to
spend absurd, romantic stories about himself (1368). But as it turns out, the narrator can't even
be in charge as a master, as we can see from his interactions with Apollon, his
condescending and infuriating servant.
Liza enters just at the point where the narrator is arguing with Apollon
over unpaid wages. It is a humiliating
moment for the narrator.
Part 2, Chapter 9
Infuriated with Liza, the narrator mocks her in recalling their
previous encounter, informing her that it was all just an act. Why is he so angry at this unoffending young
woman? Probably because she has
confronted him with the gap between his self-image and his actual
identity. The Hegelian Master/Servant
dialectic may be a good thing to discuss here since for the German Idealist
philosopher Georg Hegel, the self is founded upon confrontational moments—risk,
contradiction, dread. The self is established by struggle for recognition and
certainty, which entails withholding recognition from others, and Hegel's
famous representation of the founding of self-consciousness involves a primal
struggle to the death between two individuals, with the outcome being the
lordship of one and the enslavement or subjugation of the other, and a
consequent need for mediating their now-indirect relations through a
relationship to and with objects. But the Master/Servant dialectic can also be read, as
Alexandre Kojève and others have done, as a continuing struggle that happens
internally, inside the head of each individual rather than a physical struggle
between two individuals: a battle for self-recognition, authenticity, personal
autonomy. I suggest that success in this
endeavor would perhaps be constituted by an adequate fit between who one really
is and who one thinks one is. If that's
the right way to put it, it's clear that the narrator is not succeeding. Liza is not a blockheaded master-consciousness,
and in fact the narrator says that the relative position between himself and
this young woman had been reversed: just as she was in the subject-position at
the brothel, the weeping nervous wreck of a narrator is now in precisely that
position relative to her. He takes her
solicitude for pity, and that is unbearable to him. She is a sensitive servant-consciousness who
seems to be offering him the very recognition he craves but cannot abide. The situation is intolerable.
Part 2, Chapter 10
The narrator says that for him, love has always been a matter of dominating others, and it is the product of struggle. But then, his hatred of real-life makes it impossible to deal with the "subjugated object" (1377). Liza takes her leave, having rejected the crumpled five ruble note the narrator tried to give her as a token of his own spite, a symbol of his wish to see her as nothing more than a prostitute in spite of her genuine affection for him. In the end, writing this entire story down seems to have been punishment rather than relief. The narrator has throughout cast himself as the anti-hero, the man alienated from so-called real life. The underground seems to be the place where an unquenchable desire to engage with real life battles an equally strong desire to escape from it and forget it altogether, to disappear into heroic fictions spun by others or by oneself.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.